December 15, 2003. ץ The Emptiness of Virtue Ethics.

In November, Lawrence Solum had a good post on "Virtue Ethics", an approach to moral behavior. I thought about it while my students took their final exam this morning. This approach seems quite empty to me, though Professor Solum seemed to do a fair job of presenting it (I don't know whether he actually likes it or not). Here is what it is:

It might be illuminating to compare virtue ethics to deontology and utilitarianism via the following simplified formulas:
Formulas are tricky, and I haven't tried to get these formulations exactly right. Instead, my aim was to paint broadly to give a sense of the basic structure of these three approaches to moral theory. Whereas, utilitarianism makes consequences (or states of affairs) the central idea of moral theory and deontology focuses on moral rules, virtue ethics focuses on character and human excellence.

...

...Virtue ethics counsels us to cultivate virtue--to acquire the human excellences insofar as that is possible. Virtuous agents will then aim at the right goals in life, because their intellectual and emotional makeup naturally points them towards a just and flourishing life. Thus, a fully virtuous human will characteristically act in the right way for the right reasons. And what about those who lack full virtue? Many humans, however, lack fully virtuous characters. What counsel does virtue ethics offer those who lack the full complement of human excellence? The answer to this question can be developed in at least two ways. First, we might ask ourselves, "How would a virtuous human act in these circumstances?" This is, of course, part of ordinary human deliberation. When faced with a difficult choice situation, sometimes we think of someone whose character we admire, and ask, "How would she (or he) deal with this?" Second, we might ask ourselves, "What do the virtues counsel in this situation?" That is, we can take our understanding of the human excellences, and ask questions like, "What action would be courageous?" or "What action would accord with the virtue of justice?"

The obvious objection to virtue ethics is that it begs the question, and in not one, but two way. What should I do? I should do what a virtuous person would do.

First problem: How do I know that the person is virtuous? Answer: He always does the right thing.

Second problem: What would a virtuous person do? Answer: He would do the right thing.

Without some other ethical theory to tell us right from wrong, there is no way to know who is virtuous or what is virtuous. And if we have the other theory, we don't need virtue ethics.

I checked in another source to see if I was missing something. Rosalind Hursthouse wrote an article called Virtue Ethics for the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy ( JUL 18 2003). She very helpfully has a list of objections people raise to virtue ethics, but she doesn't have quite the one I raise above. The closest objections she presents (without necessarily agreeing with them) is that virtue ethics lacks practical application and, close to my first objection above, how we decide what a virtue is:

... the complaint that virtue ethics does not produce codifiable principles is still the most commonly voiced criticism of the approach, expressed as the objection that it is, in principle, unable to provide action-guidance.

...

What does virtue ethics have to say about dilemmas -- cases in which, apparently, the requirements of different virtues conflict because they point in opposed directions? Charity prompts me to kill the person who would be better off dead, but justice forbids it. Honesty points to telling the hurtful truth, kindness and compassion to remaining silent or even lying. What shall I do?

...

Another problem for virtue ethics, which is shared by both utilitarianism and deontology, is (iv) "the justification problem." Abstractly conceived, this is the problem of how we justify or ground our ethical beliefs, an issue that is hotly debated at the level of metaethics. In its particular versions, for deontology there is the question of how to justify its claims that certain moral rules are the correct ones, and for utilitarianism of how to justify its claim that the only thing that really matters morally is consequences for happiness or well-being. For virtue ethics, the problem concerns the question of which character traits are the virtues.

Utilitarianism is frank about this---it just says "We will assume that happiness is good, since almost everybody thinks it is, and go on from there." If someone doesn't think it is interesting to figure out what rules make people happy, then utilitarianism isn't much use to that person, of course. Virtue ethics has a much bigger problem with that attitude, though. We all say we value Courage, but we definitely don't like it when our enemies possess that virtue, and often we dislike it when our friends do, because they get themselves in trouble. In my weblog controversy, I am sure my friends wished I lacked the courage to say the things I believed.

Lawrence Solum also says,

Utilitarianism claims that there is a very simple rule (which if correctly applied) yields the morally correct action for each situation: act so as to produce the best consequences. Deontology has a similar claim: to do the right thing, simply consult the moral rules, and perform that action which is required or if no action is required, choose from among those that are permissible. Virtue ethics characteristically denies that there is any mechanical rule that generates the morally correct action. Why not? One answer to that question lies in Aristotle's idea of the phronimos, the person who possesses the virtue of practical wisdom. The phronimos has the ability to respond to the complexities of particular situations, to see what is morally salient, and to choose an action that will work given the circumstances.

This seems to me to get things exactly backwards. True, utilitarianism says that you can just follow the rule of "Maximize utility," but this is not at all a simple rule to apply, and results in highly differentiated behavior depending on the circumstances. It requires a huge amount of practical wisdom to be a precise utilitarian. The same goes for deontology, as best as I can make out. In practice, various contradictory absolute rules have to be sorted out, an impossible task I think, but if possible, one that requires practical wisdom. Virtue ethics, though, just says, "Don't worry much about the particular situation-- do what cultivates your own virtue." This is rather like rule utilitarianism.

The idea of pursuing virtue is, of course, not a bad one. It just needs some kind of supporting argument, and should not be seen as an end in itself. One thing that Professor Solum says is that

A virtue politics might begin with the idea that the goal of the state should be the establishment of the conditions for the development of human excellence.

"Virtue Politics" makes a lot of sense. It is not necessarily that virtue is the summum bonum, but that if people are virtuous, that is good for other reasons-- because it reduces crime, increases happiness, and pleases God. Rather than the state trying to make everybody obey rules by promulgating specific rules and enforcing them with criminal penalties or financial incentives, it is often wiser for the state to try to induce good behavior by encouraging virtue. One way it does this is by encouraging religion, the subject of several recent posts of mine.

[permalink, http://php.indiana.edu/~erasmuse/w/03.12.15f.htm ]

 

To return to Eric Rasmusen's weblog, click http://php.indiana.edu/~erasmuse/w/0.rasmusen.htm.